2. Do Experts Really Perceive the World Differently from Non-Experts?

People sometimes say things like the following: Cabernet Sauvignon tastes different to an expert wine taster than to a novice; or, Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony sounds different to a seasoned conductor than it does to someone just hearing it for the first time. But does wine literally taste differently (or the symphony sound differently) to the expert than to the layperson? Or is it instead that the wine tastes the same to both, but the expert is just able to make a quick cognitive inference that the wine is a Cabernet Sauvignon, while the novice cannot do this? I have to admit that when I first started reading about these cases years ago (especially in Siewert, 1998, Chapter 7.9; and Siegel, 2006), I thought that the latter view was probably right. But when I began to look into the relevant evidence from psychology and neuroscience, and the relevant literature in philosophy, I became convinced that the evidence points more towards there being genuine sensory changes due to learning and expertise. In my book, I provide a lengthy abductive argument for that conclusion (see also Prettyman, 2018). Here I’m just going to highlight some of the evidence that began to convince me.

What I saw in the philosophical literature was that, with some exceptions, there was fairly widespread convergence in the intuitions of philosophers–living at different times and places–that perceptual learning involves sensory changes. These include many historical cases, such as when the 14th-century Hindu philosopher Vedānta Deśika writes about how a person can become able to see two similar colors of a gemstone as distinct, where as a novice he saw them as the same colors (translated, Freschi, 2011, pp. 12–13). There are not just visual cases in the literature, but also cases from other sense modalities. For instance, Casey O’Callaghan (2011) and Brit Brogaard (2018) both write about how foreign spoken languages sound different to someone once she learns the language, due to perceptual learning. Furthermore, it’s not just philosophers who have these intuitions. The psychologist Eleanor Gibson, herself a pioneer in the field of perceptual learning, imagines a researcher who is unfamiliar with goats but is tasked with running experiments on them. The goats start off looking identical to him, but after a few months, he becomes able to spot a particular goat in the herd in an instant and from far away (1969, p. 82).

These are just a few of the cases mentioned in my book. But the overall picture that I found is that there is a lot of convergence across different times and places that perceptual learning involves sensory changes. While I do not think that intuitions offer definitive evidence for that conclusion, I do think that the convergent intuitions should be taken as evidence for it, at least barring countervailing evidence. This doesn’t mean that intuitions should be our only guide. But what I also found is that other bodies of evidence in psychology and neuroscience lend further credence to these intuitions. Let me turn now to some neuroscientific results.

A battery of studies on perceptual learning provide evidence of neural changes very early on in perceptual processing after perceptual learning, specifically in the primary sensory areas. For instance, Furmanski, Schluppeck, and Engel (2004) trained participants to improve their detection of a 45-degree stimulus for low contrast (i.e. faded-looking and hard to detect) stimuli presented in one of two 300-millisecond intervals.

Using fMRI, the experimenters scanned participants’ brains before and after the training. They found increased activation in the primary visual cortex after learning, when, and only when, the participants were shown the trained 45-degree stimulus. Similar changes in the primary sensory cortices have been found in perceptual learning studies on touch and on audition. These changes have also been found in perceptual learning studies on expertise, where bird experts look at pictures of birds and dog experts look at pictures of dogs.

After learning about these neuroscience studies, I started to think in terms of the following argument. If perceptual learning involves sensory changes, then we would expect changes in perceptual processing after perceptual learning. And this is precisely what the neuroscience studies above seem to show. By contrast, if perceptual learning simply involved quick cognitive inferences and not sensory changes, then we would not expect changes in perceptual processing after the learning. So, there is neuroscientific evidence for the view that perceptual learning involves genuinely sensory changes.

There are, of course, limitations to both the philosophical and neuroscientific evidence, especially when each is considered on its own. The philosophical evidence tells us about perceptual experience, but it is anecdotal and unscientific. The neuroscientific evidence is scientific, but it does not tell us about experience. Together, however, the introspective evidence and the neural evidence offer an account that is both scientific and speaks to experience.

In the next post, I turn from the nature of perceptual learning to its scope. My book explores perceptual learning in five different perceptual domains: in natural kind recognition, sensory substitution, multisensory perception, speech perception, and color perception. In the next post, I focus on the role of perceptual learning in multisensory perception.

References

Brogaard, B. (2018). In defense of hearing meanings. Synthese, 195(7), 2967– 2983.

Freschi, E. (2011). The refutation of any extra-sensory perception in Vedānta Deśika: A philosophical appraisal of Seśvaramīmāṃsā ad MS 1.1.4. Unpublished manuscript. Retrieved from https://www.ikga.oeaw.ac.at/mediawiki/images/3/3e/The_refutation_of_any_extra-sensory_perc.pdf

Furmanski, C. S., Schluppeck, D., & Engel, S. A. (2004). Learning strengthens the response of primary visual cortex to simple patterns. Current Biology, 14(7), 573– 578.

O’Callaghan, C. (2011). Against hearing meanings. Philosophical Quarterly, 61(245), 783– 807.

Prettyman, A. (2018). Perceptual learning. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, e1489.

Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception? In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 481– 503). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

Siewert, C. (1998). The significance of consciousness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Back to Top