Part 1 of The Implicit Mind makes the case that “implicit attitudes” are mental states that cause us to act in relatively spontaneous ways, sometimes for better and sometimes for worse. I offer an unorthodox description of implicit attitudes, distinguish implicit attitudes from other folk psychological kinds, and show how implicit attitudes help to explain paradigmatic cases of spontaneous action. Put a bit less formally, what I’m after in this book is an understanding of whether and how some spontaneous reactions can be better than others, and not just because of luck or fortuitous circumstances. What is happening with the person who knows how to smile reassuringly to someone in the grips of anxiety, at the right time, in the right way? But crucially, how can we understand what is happening with this person without losing sight of the similarity between her and the one who (let’s suppose) is disposed to see the very same expression on white faces as anxious but on black faces as threatening? My account of implicit attitudes is meant to make sense of these two faces of spontaneity.
Drawing on earlier work with Alex Madva (Brownstein & Madva 2012a,b), which was in turn inspired by Tamar Gendler’s (2008a,b) work on “alief,” I define implicit attitudes in terms of 4 co-activating components. These are (1) noticing a salient Feature in the ambient environment; (2) feeling an immediate, directed, and affective Tension; (3) reacting Behaviorally; and (4) moving toward Alleviation of tension in such a way that one’s spontaneous reactions can improve over time. These components, on my view, are relatively automatic and co-activating, but they are also dynamic, in the sense that agents’ “FTBA”reactions can improve over time.
Here’s an example: imagine a tennis player in the middle of a point. She registers a salient feature of her opponent’s shot, perhaps the underspin and arc of a drop shot. Her perceptual experience has an “imperatival” quality; in virtue of her goal of winning the point, it commands a particular reaction. Her reaction is shot through with a particular kind of bodily tension, one she might describe as pulling her toward the net to retrieve the short ball. If all goes well, her behavior—a hard charge to the net—will alleviate this felt tension, as she prepares to play the next shot. If she charges too hard, though, or not hard enough, her mistakes will feed back into future FTBA reactions in similar circumstances.
The core claim of Part 1 is that implicit attitudes are mental states with co-activating FTBA components. I explore the content of the perceptual experience of noticing salient features in the environment; the affective processes underlying felt tension; and prediction-error theories of learning, which I argue help to show how relatively automatic states can nevertheless improve over time. Crucially, I also map this cognitive structure onto paradigmatic examples of the vices of spontaneity, in particular, implicit biases. To return to the example from my first post, consider an encounter between a police officer and a black man, whom the officer perceives as exhibiting “furtive movement.” Noticing the man’s gesture may set off a feeling of tension as a result of associations in the officer’s mind between black male faces and the concept danger. This feeling may activate fight or flight reactions in turn, depending on the context. The outcome of the officer’s spontaneous reaction—perhaps to assume an aggressive posture or reach for a weapon—will feed back into future reactions in similar circumstances.
This description of implicit attitudes raises a thorny metaphysical question, one which has garnered considerable attention in related literature. In the taxonomy of the mind, what are these things?! Most of the debate has played out in terms of theorizing about the metaphysics of implicit bias specifically. Are implicit biases ballistic reflex-like stimulus-response reactions? Or perhaps they are associations learned on the basis of spatiotemporal contiguity. Alternatively, some have argued that implicit biases are pedestrian beliefs, perhaps conscious, perhaps unconscious. And some have suggested that they are belief-like, but not quite beliefs. While each of these approaches is consistent with relevant data on implicit social cognition, I argue that none adequately explain the full scope of the phenomenon, particularly when the full scope of the phenomenon is acknowledged to include not just morally problematic biases but useful, intelligent, and even sometimes virtuosic spontaneous inclinations (in, for example, sports and the arts).
Part 1 concludes with a discussion of the kind of “guidance” implicit attitudes might provide us in decision-making and behavior. Drawing on Hannah Ginsborg’s conception of “primitive normativity,” the final section proposes that there is normativity inherent in these states, but a kind that is only provisional, providing only pro tanto warrant for our actions. This connects up with the theme of Part 2, which questions how we relate to our spontaneous inclinations and dispositions. Are implicit attitudes “ours,” in the sense that they reflect on our character? Commonly we think of our beliefs, hopes, values, desires, and so on in these terms, as “person- level” states. Do implicit mental states reflect on who we are in this sense? Relatedly, under what conditions are we responsible for spontaneous and impulsive actions, that is, those that result from the workings of the implicit mind?
References
Brownstein, M., & Madva, A. 2012a. Ethical automaticity. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 42(1), 67– 97.
Brownstein, M., & Madva, A. 2012b. The normativity of automaticity. Mind and Language, 27(4), 410– 434.
Gendler, T. S. 2008a. Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634– 663.
Gendler, T. S. 2008b. Alief in action (and reaction). Mind and Language, 23(5), 552– 585.
Hi Michael, do you mind if I ask about the scope of this claim: “The core claim of Part 1 is that implicit attitudes are mental states with co-activating FTBA components.” What states are you saying at FTBA-structured, exactly? I mean, sometimes people index ‘implicit attitudes’ to whatever the IAT measures (if anything) but you clearly have broader interests than that? And sometimes people define it negatively as ‘any attitude that isn’t introspectively accessible’ or something, but that would seem to make your claim really really strong – that all mental states that aren’t introspectible are FTBA-structured. So is your claim just that FTBA states are an important class that explains some/much/most/all of what we’re interested in when we talk about ‘implicit attitudes’?
Hi Luke,
Thanks for your question. Part of the issue here (as you probably know) is that there are multiple overlapping definitions of “implicit attitudes,” “implicit associations,” “implicit bias,” and so on, and these cut across philosophy and psychology in often confusing ways. I went back and forth about what terms to use in the book. Ultimately, I went with “implicit attitudes” for a few reasons, but I use the term differently than many others. It’s neither my view that implicit attitudes are whatever the IAT measures nor that implicit attitudes are all introspectively unavailable states. Regarding the first idea (that implicit attitudes are whatever the IAT measures), my view is that the IAT (imperfectly) captures behavior which can be thought of as a proxy for mental processes which are components of implicit attitudes. I think the second idea (that implicit attitudes are introspectively unavailable states) is basically a non-starter, as there is too much evidence that people have awareness (of various kinds) of their implicit attitudes (both as I define them and as others do).
So, on my view, implicit attitudes just are those states with co-activating FTBA components. They’re not defined in terms of a specific psychological test or a specific characteristic (like being outside of awareness). I suppose the scope of this claim is pretty wide, then, in the sense that I think implicit attitudes are implicated in much of human thought and action.
Hope that clarifies a little.
Thanks, that does clarify – so the claim that ‘implicit attitudes are FTBA-structured’ isn’t so much an empirical hypothesis to be affirmed or denied, so much as it’s the definition of a posit that you want to show is fertile?
Yeah I think that’s right. I do think the claim that “implicit attitudes are FTBA-structured” is empirically tractable. And it’s truth or falsity will rise and fall with a whole bunch of data. But I don’t think there’s a single test that specifically quantifies what I think implicit attitudes are.
Hello there
You want quality traffic that Buys From Your Site philosophyofbrains.com or Converts into Highly Responsive Subscribers ?
I Will Promote Your Business In Worldwide To Any Niche …
– I search in google after the keyward offered by you in order to find sites;
– I will ask the site administrator if he is interested in your offer;
– The process continues on many sites until you get all the vizits promises.
I can send your offer on:
– Country Desired (only the country you specify)
– 80% TIER 1 Countries Guaranteed (USA, CA, GB, AU, NZ, IE)
– Niche Desired(only the keywords you specify)
We help you grow your business because we understand that our business growth directly depends on our ability to GROW YOUR BUSINESS.
Please follow here for more information:
https://bit.ly/Get_Traffic_That_Converts
Regards,
AxyyKo